My initial comments on
paragraphs 10-1 and 10-2 drew some insightful commentary by PhysicsGuy (see
here and
here) which compelled me to look deeper into some side issues. Turns out, the reading I had done on Anglican theology was actually written by someone who took a minority position regarding eucharistic theology. In addition to mistaking a minority position for majority consent, I was also unaware of the diversity of views within Anglicanism on how to interpret the Thirty-Nine Articles of Religion. To make the matter even more complex, upon consulting with a church historian, I discovered that there have been multiple shifts in the meanings of theological terms regarding the eucharist since the 17th century down to the 21st century. Given how far afield this takes me from the topic at hand, I don’t plan to say much more about it other than to marvel at just how fun it is to accidentally stumble back on to a topic you’ve only spent a cursory amount of time and find a whole new complex vista you never considered before!
There is one comment from PhysicsGuy that I would like to discuss more:
Physics Guy wrote: ↑Thu Jul 08, 2021 6:28 am
Anyway, if Hume's discussion of miracles is really going to begin from the idea that the Eucharist is supposed to be a frequently observed violation of the laws of nature, then he's really starting off on the wrong foot, because apart from misguided pious superstition the Eucharist has never been supposed to be that kind of physical miracle. It has always been a safely unfalsifiable metaphysical miracle.
I am going to stand by my assessment that Hume is engaging in a good strategy here, but to justify that assessment I thought it might be worthwhile to include a resource on the use of “substance” in philosophy.
The Stanford Encyclopedia entry has two paragraphs that I think help frame the issue. The author of the article gives two different senses with the first being more generic and broad:
SEP wrote:There could be said to be two rather different ways of characterising the philosophical concept of substance. The first is the more generic. The philosophical term ‘substance’ corresponds to the Greek ousia, which means ‘being’, transmitted via the Latin substantia, which means ‘something that stands under or grounds things’. According to the generic sense, therefore, the substances in a given philosophical system are those things that, according to the system, are the foundational or fundamental entities of reality. Thus, for an atomist, atoms are the substances, for they are the basic things from which everything is constructed. In David Hume’s system, impressions and ideas are the substances, for the same reason. In a slightly different way, Forms are Plato’s substances, for everything derives its existence from Forms. In this sense of ‘substance’ any realist philosophical system acknowledges the existence of substances. Probably the only theories which do not would be those forms of logical positivism or pragmatism that treat ontology as a matter of convention. According to such theories, there are no real facts about what is ontologically basic, and so nothing is objectively substance.
I would submit that this use of “substance” fits with current Roman Catholic teaching on transubstantiation. They don’t require believers to subscribe to a specific metaphysic, just that a fundamental alteration has happened to the host that changed its most basic nature. If a believer wants to understand that in terms of Thomism or Neo-Kantian metaphysics, it doesn't matter.
The second sense of the term is more narrowly construed and the details become dependent on the broader system/school of thought being utilized:
SEP wrote:The second use of the concept is more specific. According to this, substances are a particular kind of basic entity, and some philosophical theories acknowledge them and others do not. On this use, Hume’s impressions and ideas are not substances, even though they are the building blocks of—what constitutes ‘being’ for—his world. According to this usage, it is a live issue whether the fundamental entities are substances or something else, such as events, or properties located at space-times. This conception of substance derives from the intuitive notion of individual thing or object, which contrast mainly with properties and events. The issue is how we are to understand the notion of an object, and whether, in the light of the correct understanding, it remains a basic notion, or one that must be characterised in more fundamental terms. Whether, for example, an object can be thought of as nothing more than a bundle of properties, or a series of events.
This sense of “substance” is captured by the Aristotelian categories (eventually Thomistic ones) that have dominated Roman Catholic thought since the close of antiquity to the modern period.
Now I think it only proper to at least give Hume some space to declare his position in regards to “substance” and to that end I’ll quote from his
‘Treatise’: Section VI, 6-2:
Hume wrote:The idea of a substance as well as that of a mode, is nothing but a collection of simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, and have a particular name assigned them, by which we are able to recal, either to ourselves or others, that collection. But the difference betwixt these ideas consists in this, that the particular qualities, which form a substance, are commonly refer'd to an unknown something, in which they are supposed to inhere; or granting this fiction should not take place, are at least supposed to be closely and inseparably connected by the relations of contiguity and causation. The effect of this is, that whatever new simple quality we discover to have the same connexion with the rest, we immediately comprehend it among them, even though' it did not enter into the first conception of the substance. Thus our idea of gold may at first be a yellow colour, weight, malleableness, fusibility; but upon the discovery of its dissolubility in aqua regia, we join that to the other qualities, and suppose it to belong to the substance as much as if its idea had from the beginning made a part of the compound one. The principle of union being regarded as the chief part of the complex idea, gives entrance to whatever quality afterwards occurs, and is equally comprehended by it, as are the others, which first presented themselves.
Now I want to be clear here that I really appreciate PhysicsGuy’s comments, but I don’t want to make him play the role of defending religious beliefs and doctrines he doesn’t actually hold. Offering a different perspective and giving needed corrections shouldn’t come with that kind of social burden. So I’m going to draw inspiration from PhysicsGuy’s posts and create a hypothetical person who disputes my assessment of Hume’s strategy. Because I lack imagination, let us call him ChemistryCarl.
ChemistryCarl wrote: I can’t get behind calling Hume’s strategy as being “clever” at all. I think he conflates transubstantiation with real presence in the host and it leaves a bad taste in my mouth. More importantly is that transubstantiation isn’t considered a miracle and by beginning this section with that topic seems more foolish than clever.
I am forced to concede to Carl’s first point. I’m not fully convinced of it myself, but to meaningfully respond to it would require me to go much deeper into the writings of 18th century Christian theology to fully sort out and if it is one thing I’ve learned from watching Mormon Apologists is, dying for every hill is just stupid. So let’s chalk that up to a mistake on Hume’s part.
The second point I think misses the thrust of Hume’s strategy. I’m pretty comfortable with allowing a believer to say, “We have particular ways of understanding what miracles are and have finely graded distinctions concerning them, transubstantiation doesn’t meet the criteria for a miracle.” That’s cool and I can respect that, though I want to point out that the spirit of Hume’s comments thus far doesn’t actually need transubstantiation to be called a miracle to work.
Think a moment about what transubstantiation is all about. It is part of this ritual where a priest says a formulaic prayer over common bread and wine which God responds to by altering the fundamental reality of the bread and wine to match that of the flesh and blood of Jesus Christ. Now we may not classify that as a miracle on technical grounds, but it is still an event where God directly interacts with bread and wine, to change them in a way they wouldn’t normally change if left on their own.
Hume advises us that a “wise man, therefore, proportions his belief to the evidence”. Adopting Hume’s point of view here, what evidence do we have? Well we have no evidence from our senses because the change that takes place in the bread and wine happens on a level that we can’t perceive, even through instrumentation. All that we have left then is that evidence of testimony supplied by scripture and tradition, but Protestants vociferously contest that and in such a manner that it doesn’t look as if the Roman interpretation could be considered overwhelmingly better.
What sort of options does ChemistryCarl have in terms of responding to Hume? Empirically confirming transubstantiation is off the table and all sides seem to agree on that. ChemistryCarl could decide that the historical argument for transubstantiation is damn near watertight and proceed along those lines. There is also a third option where ChemistryCarl, which disputes Hume’s broader philosophy and argues that Hume is creating a false dilemma by not allowing for a rational argumentation from a non-empirical metaphysic.
I think that third option is what Hume wants, to quote the
closing paragraph of the ‘Enquiry’:
Hume wrote:When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.
(Illustration of David Hume by Cassio Loredano)